Book
Review: Manuel
Castells’ Trilogy The Information Age: Economy, Society and
Culture.
Volume 1. The Rise of the Network Society (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996),
pp. xvii + 556.
Volume 2. The Power of Identity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), pp. xv
+ 461.
Volume 3. End of Millennium (Oxford: Blackwell, 1998), pp. xiv +
418.
By Steve Fuller <Steve.Fuller@durham.ac.uk>
Manuel
Castells’ massive trilogy, “The Information Age”,
is rapidly becoming unavoidable (though not necessarily easy) reading
for anyone trying to understand what Castells himself calls the
age of “informationalism.” The following review, which
appeared in “Science, Technology, and Human Values”
(official journal of the Society for Social Studies of Science)
in the December 1998 issue, is by Steve Fuller of Durham University,
England.
The critical
response to this trilogy has so far betrayed signs of short-term
historical memory loss of the sort associated with IT intoxication.
For example, Anthony Giddens begins his review of the first volume
in The Times Higher Education Supplement: “We live today in
a period of intense and puzzling transformation, signaling perhaps
a move beyond the industrial era altogether. Yet where are the great
sociological works that chart this transition?” When this
question was first posed a quarter century ago, the obvious answer
was Daniel Bell’s The Coming of Postindustrial Society (1973),
the single work most responsible for displaying the impending social,
political and economic relevance of information technology. Yet,
despite Bell’s clear historic significance, he remains a shadowy
figure, typically written out of sociology textbooks and paid only
lip service even in texts (such as Castells’) specifically
concerned with the “informatization” of society. An
important reason for the silent treatment is that Bell underwent
a highly publicized transformation from Trotskyism in the early
1950s, through a series of disillusionments with the American labor
movement and leftist intellectuals, which culminated in a staunch
defense of the universities in the face of student revolts in the
late 1960s and early 1970s. The unpronounced verdict is that Bell
betrayed the left and has since then refused to seek redemption.
However, over the years, Bell suggested that the potential of computers
to store, process and distribute knowledge was instrumental to his
conclusion that a revolutionary vanguard with a distinct “proletarian
standpoint” was obsolete. Soon, no genuinely valuable form
of knowledge would be restricted to a particular class, and in any
case, no class could be entrusted with producing genuinely valuable
knowledge.
I mention Bell’s
career as an introduction to Castells because to admit—as
both Bell and Castells do—that information technology has
become the principal mode of production and perhaps even legitimation
in today’s world is to seriously challenge the Marxist proposition
that emancipatory knowledge is integrally tied to class position.
Not surprisingly, perhaps, over the past 30 years, Castells’
own career has also metamorphosed quite noticeably. Beginning as
a Marxist specializing in urban grassroots politics, Castells is
now a highly sought after advisor on the world’s changing
socioeconomic order who is based in one of the U.S.’s premier
universities. He has been a member of the European Commission’s
High Level Expert Group on the Information Society and, in 1992,
was invited (along with three collaborators, one of whom is now
president of Brazil) to advise Boris Yeltsin on political economic
policy. To be sure, very much like Bell, Castells has taken pains
to ensure the academic integrity of his activities (especially in
terms of restricting the sources of his research income).
The plot structure
of the 1500 pages under review is framed in terms of a dialectic
that encapsulates “informationalism,” which Castells
defines as capitalism’s final frontier. Volumes 1 and 2 of
the trilogy usefully separate the “thesis” and “antithesis”—“network”
versus “identity”—while Volume 3 offers less a
resolution than a recapitulation and update of this tension. The
prehistory of the dialectic consists of the efforts taken by the
major nation states at the height of the Cold War to increase their
surveillance and military capabilities. They constructed vast electronic
information and communication networks, which with the decline of
superpower hostilities have unwittingly provided the means to enable
large corporations and, increasingly, special interest groups and
private individuals to destabilize and even dismantle both state
power and the norms of civil society. (The breakdown of the Roman
Empire into feudal fiefdoms and free cities comes to mind as a historical
precedent.) However, this electronic subversion of the social order
has exacted its own toll from the subversives. Basically, the network
mentality strips both firms and individuals of any secure sense
of identity. Thus, we see the decline of career employment and the
conversion of corporations to investment companies. Nothing can
get done unless you become a node in a network, but once the job
is done, new jobs force the nodes into new network configurations.
Both human and corporate life thus comes to defined by the “project.”
The only way to check this reduced sense of identity is to extend
the life of the project indefinitely, which serves to revive the
fortunes of social movements that are fueled by a nonnegotiable
sense of resistance or “identity politics.” The various
fundamentalisms, insurgencies, and lifestyles that pepper the political
landscape of our times take full advantage of the network’s
flexible infrastructure to combat their oppressors, both real and
virtual. But unlike culture-based resistance to global capitalism
in the 19th century, these movements do not aim for territorial
sovereignty backed by a strong state. Such a prospect is seen as
undesirable as a future of force-fed McDonaldization. The communities
defined by identity politics exist in virtual space and online time.
Their presence is felt mainly in their ability to shape the code
through which all network transactions occur. For, whereas the informational
capitalists treat the network in purely strategic and instrumental
terms, the new social movements rely on the network for their sense
of solidarity and hence may turn out to be the gatekeepers of the
network’s democratic potential.
This brings
us to the end of Volume 2. Readers of Castells’ last major
work, The Informational City (1988), may justifiably wonder what
The Network Society Castells’ designation of the Mexican Zapatistas
as an “informational guerilla movement” (Vol. 2, p.
79) has already become grist for the social theory mill (see P.
McNaughten and J. Urry, Contested Natures, 1998). After all, the
Zapatista strategy of winning the war of global public opinion by
the Internet—and that victory affecting the outcome of the
flesh-and-blood war at home—goes a good way toward remediating
Jean Baudrillard’s remarks about the “simulated”
character of the Persian Gulf War. But a more significant feature
of this volume is Castells’ remarkably evenhanded treatment
of “new social movements.” For such social theorists
du jour as Ulrich Beck, these movements constitute the locally fragmented
successors of world socialism. In contrast, Castells readily includes
fundamentalist Islam and Christianity in their number, thereby complicating
the political implications of the resistance to global informationalism.
Instead of reducing fundamentalism to traditionalism, Castells,
to his credit, highlights how the tools of the putative oppressors
can be used for liberatory ends. However, the ease with which Castells
removes the distinctly ideological character of these movements
from his analysis—by defining them in terms of their common
relationship to information technology—suggests a level of
detachment that may have dulled his political sensibility. This
point turns out to have a special poignancy, given Castells’
own recent efforts at advising policymakers.
Having read
the first two volumes of The Information Age six months before the
third, I did not expect Castells to conclude the trilogy on a downbeat
note. Rather, I supposed that he would continue to sustain the dialectic
between network and identity, perhaps blandly predicting that pockets
of resistance would thrive in the midst of global capital expansion.
However, any whiff of “have your cake and eat it” is
quickly dispelled in the Introduction to End of Millennium. Here
Castells makes clear that he originally underestimated the ability
of a globally networked criminal economy to pick up the slack left
by a downsized and debilitated system of nation states. The breakdown
of law and order in the former Soviet Union is his personal case
in point, which returns us to the advice that Castells and his colleagues
gave Yeltsin in 1992. Unfortunately, this crucial point for understanding
the trilogy’s normative orientation is buried in Chapter 3,
footnote 39. Here we learn that Castells told Yeltsin that if legal
and other institutional safeguards were not first put in place,
a privatized economy would return Russia to a veritable state of
nature. But because Yeltsin’s economic advisors seemed to
associate such safeguards with a continuation of the dreaded socialist
regime, they unintentionally opened the door to the mafia culture
that currently holds Russia in its grip, typically with help from
abroad. And this may be only the beginning. Much of Volume 3 is
spent conjuring up the intriguing, albeit horrific, spectre of information
technology enabling the coordination of criminal cartels that shadow,
penetrate and ultimately elude the regulation of capital flows,
to which everything else is becoming connected. The resulting picture
looks very much like the Manichaean struggle between the Forces
of Good and Evil that have framed so many action hero plots since
the Great Depression. The likes of Batman rarely battled an alternative
regime, but rather an anti-regime that thrived on disorder. However,
the 21st century Batperson will need to be more than a hacker with
extraordinary cryptographic and computational skills; he or she
will also require considerable political skills, since the decline
of welfare provision will remove any overriding reason for those
left behind by the informational revolution to support existing
governments. This emerging “fourth world,” in Castells’
terms, is the wild card that holds the fate of the next century.
I find this
picture quite compelling, but it would be easy to see how a reader
of just The Network Society could be left with the impression that
Castells endorses the illusory neoliberal future that Yeltsin’s
advisors embraced. For, while Castells says early on (Vol. 1, p.
9) that the state is the greatest determinant of technological change,
he more persistently observes that the sovereignty of the nation_
state is perhaps in irreversible decline. Moreover, since Castells
manages to tie changes in virtually every dimension of social life—from
intimate relations to financial flows—to the innovation and
diffusion of information technology, his self-styled “circumspection”
(Vol. 3, p. 359) on political matters can leave the impression that
not much can be done at the level of public policy to alter the
forward momentum of technological change. Indeed, he even claims
that the specific origins of the latest wave of the IT revolution
in Silicon Valley, California, has anchored the revolution’s
subsequent development (Vol. 1, p. 5).
Consider how
Castells handles the deepening of global class divisions resulting
from the polarization of info rich and info_ poor. (Vol. 1, p. 220ff).
For the first two volumes, Castells accentuates the positive side
of this development. The growing number of highly skilled workers
in most nations—including those of the Third World—leads
him to conclude that, gloomy forecasts notwithstanding, informationalism
does not impose any additional barriers to social mobility and may
even remove some traditional ones, especially as defined by the
boundaries of nation states. Certainly, informationalism must be
credited with the rapid economic growth experienced by certain parts
of India and East Asia. However, the transnational nature of networking
also means that the rich are more than ever capable of shutting
out the concerns of the poor in their own countries, as their interests
are increasingly tied to the efforts of fellow elites in other parts
of the world. Castells catches this point—an extension of
dependency theory—in Volume 3.
However, what
Castells completely misses is that the overall increase in high
skilled labor means that the value of being highly skilled declines,
which in effect makes any given member of the “elite”
more dispensable than ever. Matters are hardly helped by the accelerated
drive for technological innovation that is generally celebrated
by Castells. That merely threatens to render obsolete the very idea
of skills that can be profitably deployed over the course of a lifetime.
In that respect, informationalism’s openness to “lifelong
learning” backhandedly acknowledges the inability of even
the best schooling to shelter one from the vicissitudes of the new
global marketplace. Education, though more necessary than ever,
appears much like a vaccine that must be repeatedly taken in stronger
doses to ward off more virulent strains of the corresponding disease—in
this case, technologically induced unemployment. If there is an
adaptive group in this environment, it is those who endure the entire
gamut of the educational system without taking it too seriously.
Not surprisingly, informationalism’s entrepreneurs are drawn
precisely from this group. It would seem that the time is ripe to
reinvent Thorstein Veblen’s critique of the “learned
incapacities” of academic class.
The sheer magnitude
of ambition and achievement of Castells’ trilogy has led Giddens
in his THES review to compare The Information Age to Max Weber’s
unfinished masterwork Economy and Society. Marx’s three volume
Capital also has also been invoked (by Castells’ former Berkeley
collaborator, Peter Hall) as a reference point. Moreover, Castells
himself invites comparisons to both (Weber in Vol. 1, p. 195 ff;
Marx in Vol. 3, p. 358). It would be presumptuous to assess such
comparisons now, not least since Marx and Weber were themselves
dead before their own works acquired classic status. Nevertheless,
some remarks are in order about changes in the material conditions
that enable someone like Castells to emerge as a potential successor
to Marx and Weber in the “grand theory” sweepstakes
at the end of the millennium. Here we must return to that institution
whose absence from Castells’ “encyclopedic” account
of our times is most conspicuous: the university. Castells’
example demonstrates that the social sciences have caught up with
the natural sciences in requiring considerable economic capital
in order to accumulate what Pierre Bourdieu calls “symbolic
capital”. As economists might say, the “entry costs”
for grand theorizing have become so high that most people are shut
out from the outset. To put it in Castells’ own terms, universities
are increasingly divided into the “info rich” and the
“info poor,” and Castells clearly belongs to the former,
which is tantamount to the theorizing class. Aside from his access
to underlabouring graduate students and colleagues, Castells has
acquired an ability to travel to most of the places he talks about,
which cannot be reciprocated by most of the residents of those places.
No doubt many of them would like to know how informationalism has
affected his practices, but their inability to find out constitutes
an epistemic asymmetry that enables Castells to enjoy the materialist
equivalent of a transcendental standpoint on the world’s affairs.
All the more
interesting, then, that Castells turns Marx’s Eleventh Thesis
on Feuerbach on its head by saying that philosophers of the future
should interpret the world differently rather than trying to change
it (Vol. 3, p. 359). Interpretation turns out to be much more expensive
than action in the information age. Thus, the reader should presume
only a false modesty when Castells says, “Theory and research,
in general as well as in this book, should be considered as a means
for understanding our world, and should be judged exclusively on
their accuracy, rigor, and relevance” (Vol. 3, p. 359). Given
the costliness of judging Castells by the first two criteria, I
suppose that we shall have to concentrate on the third, and here
Marx’s Eleventh Thesis may still come in handy.
Steve Fuller
University of Durham
Steve Fuller
is Professor of Sociology & Social Policy at the University
of Durham. The latest installment in his research program, social
epistemology, is Science (Milton Keynes and Minneapolis: Open University
and University of Minnesota Presses, 1997). He would like to thank
Bill Dutton, Brian Loader and Sujatha Raman for very useful comments
on an earlier draft of this review.
|