Shorter
Hours, Free Time & the Dogma of Work (page
1 of 2)
Excerpt from `The Jobless Future'
By Stanley Aronowitz & William DiFazio
Even when one-third
of the U.S. labor force was officially unemployed throughout
the 1930s, and many workers were on short-time schedules,
they still blamed themselves for their joblessness. There
was no dignity for those who could not find jobs; the conventional
wisdom, shaken for more than a decade but not displaced,
was that there was "always" plenty of work for
those who wanted it.
This homily derives
from the larger American ideology according to which there
cannot, by definition, be a disjunction between broad economic
growth and jobs. Individuals, not the economic and social
system, are ultimately responsible for their fate; the market
adjusts itself at a level approximating full employment,
and any joblessness is "frictional" -- that is,
temporary -- for responsible and able-bodied individuals.
This key precept of the dominant ideology resumed its virtually
uncontested hegemony after World War II, when official statistics
recorded jobless rates of less than 6 percent until the
early 1980s.
There are, of
course, exceptions to the universal principle of paid labor
as the sole path to male (and, increasingly, female) dignity,
but these turn out to be only variations on the theme that
work is a "need." One may retain "dignity"
if income has been "earned" through past usury
or ownership of business. Unwork becomes dignified only
if income is derived from retirement or disability. The
implicit assumption is that the retired and the disabled
would have remained in the paid labor force if they were
able-bodied or younger. Retirement is still considered a
reward for a lifetime of faithful paid work, although some
research has contended that relatively few retirees in the
United States prosper unless they have income acquired through
labor or property in addition to their Social Security benefits.
From the standpoint of the conventional ethic, paid labor
is considered optional for women. ....
Contrary to the
ideologically conditioned theory shared by sociologists,
psychologists, and policy analysts that "nonwork"
produces, and is produced by, social disorganization and
is symbolic of irresponsibility and personal dysfunctionality,
recipients of guaranteed annual income who are relieved
of most obligations to engage in labor do not fall apart.
The incidence of alcoholism, divorce and other social ills
associated with conditions of dysfunctionality does not
increase among men who are not working. Nor do they tend
to experience higher rates of mortality than those of comparable
age who are engaged in full-time work. Given the opportunity
to engage in active nonwork, they choose this option virtually
every time.1 For example, East Coast longshoremen who are
not working but receive adequate income find many things
to occupy their time. Many spend more time with their families,
some engage in side businesses, and others take up hobbies
or fix up the house. They retain their community and much
of its culture. Most important, they are happier because
they do not have to labor every day at a hard, often life-threatening
job where the dangers associated with loading and unloading
cargo are compounded by the need to handle materials that
are frequently hazardous to their health.
Because of the
pleasures of nonwork -- work in the specific sense used
here, paid labor under a hierarchical management system
-- the men are not pleased to be called in to put in a day's
labor.
Most of all,
they have regained "free" time. This freedom,
perhaps more than the activities in which they had become
absorbed as an alternative to paid labor, fulfills the premier
promise of technological displacement that in its earlier
ideological expressions was heralded by the labor movement
and intellectuals as the main historical benefit of industrialization.
An alarming number of workers, both intellectual and manual,
surrender nearly all their waking and even dreaming hours
to labor. The by now ancient slogan of the movement for
shorter hours -- "eight hours work, eight hours sleep,
and eight hours to do with what we will" -- has been
abandoned. The notion of free time is as distant from most
people's everyday experience as open space. Labor has been
dispersed into all corners of the social world, eating space
and time, crowding out any remnants of civil society that
remained after the advent of consumer society, and colonizing
the live world. We are able neithe to play; unlike the older
industrial model where labor was experienced as an imposition
from above, the dispersal of work makes the enemy invisible
because labor is now experienced as a compulsion dictated
by economic anxiety more than by the "need" to
work.
The Need
to Reduce Working Hours
There has been
no significant reduction in working hours since the implementation
of the eight-hour day through collective bargaining and
the 1938 enactment of the federal wage and hour law. Since
then, we have witnessed a slow increase of working time
despite the most profoundly labor-displacing era of technological
change since the industrial revolution. People are laboring
their lives away, which, perhaps as much as unemployment
and poverty, has resulted in many serious family and health
problems. In turn, lengthening of working hours has contributed
to unemployment and poverty among those excluded from the
labor system.
Therefore,
there is an urgent need for a sharp reduction in the workweek
from its current forty hours -- a reduction of, initially,
at least ten hours. The thirty-hour workweek at no reduction
in pay would create new jobs only if overtime was eliminated
for most categories of labor. And, although some people
may prefer flexible working arrangements that are more compatible
with child-rearing needs or personal preference, the basic
workday should, to begin with, be reduced to six hours,
both as a health and safety measure and in order to provide
more freedom from labor in everyday life. Finally, we envision
a progressive reduction of working hours as a technological
transformation and the elinimation of what might be termed
makework in both private and public employment reduces the
amount of labor necessary for the production of goods and
services. That is, productivity gains would not necessarily,
as in the past, be shared between employers and employees
in the form of increased income, but first in fewer laboring
hours.
Obviously,
restricting laboring hours raises some important questions:
How do families maintain their living standards if income
is substantially reduced by restricting overtime and other
work-sharing arrangements? Will people use free time to
develop their capacities or will time be absorbed destructively?
Who will pay for work-sharing? Is it feasible in a global
economy where capital moves freely in search of cheap labor?
... More >>